The modern death penalty presents a puzzle: Law and norms heavily constrain how U.S. jurisdictions impose death sentences, but not how they select death row inmates for executions. In this Article, I explain why this strange void persists, argue that its presence undermines equality, and offer workable institutional responses. In short, I advance a comprehensive theory of the American execution queue—the process by which death penalty jurisdictions decide which condemned inmates will actually die.
My first objective is explanatory. Because executing a death row inmate now entails both significant litigation and extensive coordination among weakly motivated state institutions, the process takes ten times as long as it did fifty years ago. Modern executions have become “scarce,” as U.S. jurisdictions simply cannot kill all of their condemned offenders. Even though a state must make choices, there are no rules for choosing. Because there is little consensus around decisionmaking criteria, the process operates with few constraints. By the time the state must decide which condemned inmates to execute, the capacity of familiar decisionmaking criteria to meaningfully sort inmates by death- worthiness—things like offense conduct, blame, or future dangerousness—has been exhausted during prior phases of the capital punishment sequence.
My second objective is normative. I specify several preferred institutional design strategies, anchored to interests in legitimacy, transparency, fairness, and equality. First, jurisdictions should centralize the process by which they select death row inmates for executions; localities should have no role in setting execution dates. Second, a centralized entity should engage in informal (notice-and-comment) rulemaking in order to develop transparent, legitimate selection criteria. Third, jurisdictions should separate the power to determine execution priority from the power to schedule execution dates. By shifting to a centralized process grounded in transparent rulemaking and rational decisionmaking criteria, jurisdictions can curb the arbitrariness that plagues the existing system.
* Professor of Law, University of Maryland School of Law. For their assistance with various elements of this Article, I thank Frank Baumgartner, Jeffrey Belin, Richard Boldt, Josh Bowers, Danielle Citron, Erin Collins, David Dow, Kimberly Ferzan, Brandon Garrett, Adam Gershowitz, Mark Graber, David Gray, Rachel Harmon, David Jaros, Joseph Kennedy, Corinna Lain, Allison Larsen, Kay Levine, Mike Pappas, Jana Singer, Jordan Steiker, and Ronald Wright. I also thank participants in the Criminal Justice Roundtable at the University of Virginia and the Legal Theory Workshop at the University of Maryland.